Creative Evolution
ave hitherto concerned us. Such is the object of the present chapter. It will afford us the opportunity of removing certain objections, of clearing up certai
ses, is limited to taking, at intervals, views that are instantaneous and by that very fact immobile of the becoming of matter. Consciousness, being in its turn formed on the intellect, sees clearly of the inner life what is already made, and only feels confusedly the making. Thus, we pluck out of duration those moments that interest us, and that we have gathered along its course. These alone we retain. And we are right in so doing, while action only is in question. But when, in speculating on the na
e in question is purely relative to the direction in which our attention is engaged, for we are immersed in realities and cannot pass out of them; only, if the present reality is not the one we are seeking, we speak of the absence of this sought-for reality wherever we find the presence of another. We thus express what we have as a function of what we want. This is quite legitimate in the sphere of action. But, whether we will or no, we keep
entirely practical. It corresponds to the disappointment of a certain expectation, and it does not denote the absence of all order, but only the presence of that order which does not offer us actual interest. So that whenever we try to deny order completely, absolutely, we find that we are leaping from one kind of order to the other indefinitely, and that the supposed suppression of the one and the other implies the presence of the two. Indeed, if we go on, and persist in shutting our eyes to this movement of the mind and all it involves, we are no longer dealing with an idea; all that is left of disord
than I ask myself why I exist; and when I take account of the intimate connection in which I stand to the rest of the universe, the difficulty is only pushed back, for I want to know why the universe exists; and if I refer the universe to a Principle immanent or transcendent that supports it or creates it, my thought rests on this principle only a few moments, for the same problem recurs, this time in its f
thing, and being has come by superaddition to it. Or, yet again, if something has always existed, nothing must always have served as its substratum or receptacle, and is therefore eternally prior. A glass may have always been full, but the liquid it contains nevertheless fills a void. In the same way, being may have always been there, but the nought
hing, I find no answer; but that a logical principle, such as A=A, should have the power of creating itself, triumphing over the nought throughout eternity, seems to me natural. A circle drawn with chalk on a blackboard is a thing which needs explanation: this entirely physical existence has not by itself wherewith to vanquish non-existence. But the "logical essence" of the circle, that is to say, the possibility of drawing it according to a certain law-in short, its definition-is a thing which appears to me eternal: it has neither place nor date; for nowhere, at no moment, has the drawing of a circle begun to be possible. Suppose, then, that the principle on which all things rest, and which all things manifest possesses an existence of the same nature asre raised around it would become pseudo-problems. The hypothesis of an absolute that acts freely, that in an eminent sense endures, would no longer raise up intel
." To represent "Nothing," we must either imagine it or conceive it.
ousness itself. I will reduce more and more the sensations my body sends in to me: now they are almost gone; now they are gone, they have disappeared in the night where all things else have already died away. But no! At the very instant that my consciousness is extinguished, another consciousness lights up-or rather, it was already alight: it had arisen the instant before, in order to witness the extinction of the first; for the first could disappear only for another and in the presence of another. I see myself annihilated only if I have already resuscitated myself by an act which is positive, however involuntary and unconscious. So, do what I will, I am always perceiving something, either from without or from within. When I no longer know anything of external objects, it is because I have taken refuge in the consciousness that I have of myself. If I abolis
nt, at equal distance from both, in which it seems to us that we no longer perceive the one, and that we do not yet perceive the other: it is there that the image of "Nothing" is formed. In reality, we then perceive both, having reached the point where the two terms come together, and the image of Nothing, so defined, is an image full
tes, although we do not see it in imagination: it is enough that we can clearly represent the possibility of constructing it. So with the idea of the annihilation of everything. Nothing simpler, it will be said, than the procedure by which we construct the idea of it. There is, in fact, not a single object of our experience that we canno
or an opaque circle-but not a square circle, because the law of the generation of the circle excludes the possibility of defining this figure with straight lines. So my mind can represent any existing thing whatever as annihilated;-but if the annihilation of anything by the mind is an operation whose mechanism implies that it works on a part of
to speak, the void of itself. A being unendowed with memory or prevision would not use the words "void" or "nought;" he would express only what is and what is perceived; now, what is, and what is perceived, is the presence of one thing or of another, never the absence of anything. There is absence only for a being capable of remembering and expecting. He remembered an object, and perhaps expected to encounter it again; he finds another, and he expresses the disappointment of his expectation (an expectation sprung from recollection) by saying that he no longer finds anything, that he encounters "nothing." Even if he did not expect to encounter the object, it is a possible expectation of it, it is still the falsification of his eventual expectation that he expresses by saying that the object is no longer where it was. What he perceives in reality,
ppose that I sleep without dreaming or that I have ceased to exist; but at the very instant when I make this supposition, I conceive myself, I imagine myself watching over my slumber or surviving my annihilation, and I give up perceiving myself from within only by taking refuge in the perception of myself from without. That is to say that here again the full always succeeds the full, and that an intelligence that was only intelligence, that had neither regret nor desire, whose movement was governed by the movement of its object, could not even conceive an absence or a void. The conc
in short, annihilation signifies before anything else substitution, the idea of an "annihilation of everything" is as absurd as that of a square circle. The absurdity is not obvious, because there exists no particular object that cannot be supposed annihilated; then, from the fact that there is nothing to prevent each thing in turn being suppressed in thought, we conclude tha
sappearance is that of a phenomenon that is produced in space or at least in time, that consequently it still implies the calling up of an image, and that it is precisely here that we have to free ourselves from the imagination in order to appeal to the pure understanding. "Let us therefore no longer speak," it will be said, "of disappearance or annihilation; these are physical operations. Let us no longer represent the object A as annihilated or absent. Let us say simply that we think it "non-existent." To annihilate it is to act on it in time and perhaps also in
ted from the rest of things. We shall see that it carries with it, whether we will or no, all that we tried to abstract
think the object and consequently to think it existent; it is then to think that another reality, with which it is incompatible, supplants it. Only, it is useless to represent this latter reality explicitly; we are not concerned with what it is; it is enough for us to know that it drives out the object A, which alone is of interest to us. That is why we think of the expulsion rather than of the cause which expels. But this cause is none the less present to the mind; it is there in the implicit state, that which expels being inseparable from the expulsion as the hand which drives the pen is inseparable from the pen-stroke. The act by which we declare an object unreal therefore posits the existence of the real in general. In other words, to represent an object as unreal cannot consist in depriving it of every kind of existence, since the representation of an object is necessarily that of the object existing. Such an act consists simply in declaring that the existence attached
hink of anything or let us think of the totality of things, and then write in the margin of our thought the 'not,' which prescribes the rejection of what it contains: we annihilate everything mentally by the mere fact of decreeing its annihilation."-Here we have it! The very root of all the difficulties and errors with which we are confronted is to be found in the power ascribed here to negation. We represent negation as exactly symmetrical with affirmation. We imagine that negation, like affirmation, is self-sufficient. So that negation, like affirmation, would have the power of creating ideas, with this sole difference that they would be negative ideas. By affirming one thing, and then a
e of white. It is therefore, at bottom, not on the table itself that I bring this judgment to bear, but rather on the judgment that would declare the table white. I judge a judgment and not the table. The proposition, "This table is not white," implies that you might believe it white, that you did believe it such, or that I was going to believe it such. I warn you or myself that this judgment is to be replaced by another (which, it is true, I leave undete
his guard. He was affirming something: we tell him he ought to affirm something else (though without specifying the affirmation which must be substituted). There is no longer then, simply, a person and an object; there is, in face of the object, a person speaking to a person, opposing him and aiding him at the sa
the necessity of a substitution. As to what you ought to substitute for your affirmation, I tell you nothing, it is true. This may be because I do not know the color of the table; but it is also, it is indeed even more, because the white color is that alone that interests us for the moment, so that I only need to tell you that some other color will have to be substituted fo
r affirmation, whose content I do not specify, will have to be substituted for the one I find before me. Now, in neither of these two acts is there anything but affirmation. The sui generis character of negation is due to superimposing the first of these acts upon the second. It is in
ct the possible object into a real object, we shall be mistaken, and that the possible of which I am speaking is excluded from the actual reality as incompatible with it. Judgments that posit the non-existence of a thing are therefore judgments that formulate a contrast between the possible and the actual (that is, between two kinds of existence, one thought and the other found), where a person, real or imaginary, wrongly believes that a certain possible is realized. Instead of this possible, there is a reality that differs from it and rejects it: the negative judgment expresses this contrast, but it expresses the contrast in an intentionally incomplete form, because it is addressed to a person who is supposed to be interested exclusively in the possible that is indicated, and is not concerned to know by what kind of reality the possible is replaced. The expre
y the same conventional words. In both cases we can say indeed that the proposition aims at a social and pedagogical end, since the first would propagate a truth as the second would prevent an error. From this point of view, which is that of formal logic, to affirm and to deny are indeed two mutually symmetrical acts, of which the first establishes a relation of agreement and the second a relation of disagreement between a subject and an attribute. But how do we fail to see that the symmetry is altogether external and the likeness superficial? Suppose language fallen into disuse, society dissolved, every intellectual initiative, every faculty of self-reflection and of self-judgment atrophied in man: the dampness of the ground will subsist none the less, capable of inscribing itself automatically in sensation and o
e been formulated by an intelligent fish, who had never perceived anything but the wet. It would be necessary, it is true, that this fish should have risen to the distinction between the real and the possible, and that he should care to anticipate the error of his fellow-fishes, who doubtless consider as alone possible the condition of wetness in which they actually live. Keep strictly to the terms of the proposition, "The ground is not damp," and you will find that it means two things: (1) that one might believe that the ground is damp, (2) that the dampness is replaced in fact by a certain quality x. This quality is left indeterminate, either because we have no positive knowledge of it, or because it has no actual interest for the person to whom the negation is addressed. To deny, therefore, always consists in presenting in an abridged form a system of two affirmations: the one determinate, which applies to a certain possible; the other indeterminate, referring to the un
ation. Such a mind would see facts succeed facts, states succeed states, things succeed things. What it would note at each moment would be things existing, states
only note the present state of the passing reality; it will represent the passing as a change, and therefore as a contrast between what has been and what is. A
t. To represent that a thing has disappeared, it is not enough to perceive a contrast between the past and the present; it is necessary besides to turn our back
ver it. The idea arises when the phenomenon of substitution is cut in two by a mind which considers only the first half, because that alone interests it. Suppress al
been. And we must express this contrast as a function of what might have been, and not of what is; we must affirm the existence of the actual while looking only at the possible. The formula we thus obtain no longer e
t the negative form of negation benefits by the affirmation at the bottom of it. Bestriding the positive solid reality to which it is attached, this phantom objectifies itself. Thus is formed the idea of the void or of a partial nought, a thing being supposed to be replaced, not by another thing, but by a void which it leaves, that is, by the negation of itself. Now, as this operation works on anything whatever, we suppose it performed on each thing in turn, and finally on all things in block. We thus obtain
ic form to negation. The greatest philosophic difficulties arise, as we have said, from the fact that the forms of human action venture outside of their proper sphere. We are made in order to act as much as, and more than, in order to think-or rather, when we follow the bent of our nature, it is in order to act that we think. It is therefore no wonder that the habits of action give their tone to those of thought, and that our mind always perceives things in the same order in which we are accustomed to picture them when we propose to act on them. Now, it is unquestionable, as we remarked above, that every human action has its starting-point in a dissatisfaction, and thereby in a feeling of absence. We should not act if we did not set before ourselves an end, and we seek a thing only because we feel the lack of it. Our action proceeds thus from "nothing" to "something," and its very essence is to embroider "something" on the canvas of "nothing." The truth is that the "nothing" concerned here is the absence not so much of a thing as of a utility. If I bring a visitor into a room that I have not yet furnished, I say to him that "there is nothing in it." Yet I know the room is full of air; but, as we do not sit on air, the room truly contains nothing that at
And, consequently, a static conception of the real is forced on us: everything appears given once for all, in eternity. But we must accustom ourselves to think being directly, without making a detour, without first appealing to the phantom of the nought which interposes itself between it and us. We must strive to see i
e trying to approach duration: we must install ourselves within it straight away. This is what the
ess or reach it only confusedly. Let us consider a very simple act, like that of lifting the arm. Where should we be if we had to imagine beforehand all the elementary contractions and tensions this act involves, or even to perceive them, one by one, as they are accomplished? But the mind is carried immediately to the end, that is to say, to the schematic and simplified vision of the act supposed accomplished. Then, if no antagonistic idea neutralizes the effect of the first idea, the app
If matter appeared to us as a perpetual flowing, we should assign no termination to any of our actions. We should feel each of them dissolve as fast as it was accomplished, and we should not anticipate an ever-fleeting future. In order that our acti
as the second our faculty of acting. The organism thus evidences, in a visible and tangible form, the perfect accord of perception and action. So if our activity always aims at a result into which it is momentaril
cerned with mobility alone. In the smallest discernible fraction of a second, in the almost instantaneous perception of a sensible quality, there may be trillions of oscillations which repeat themselves. The permanence of a sensible quality consists in this repetition of movements, as the persistence of life consists in a series of palpitations. The primal function of perception is precisely to grasp a series of elementary changes under the form of a quality or of a simple state, by a work of condensation. The greater the power of acting bestowed upon an animal species, the more numerous, probably, are the elementary changes that its faculty of perceiving concentrates into one of its instants. And the progress must be continuous, in nature, from the beings that vibrate almost in u
se it constitutes a relatively closed system-is the living body; it is, moreover, for it that we cut out the others within the whole. Now, life is an evolution. We concentrate a period of this evolution in a stable view which we call a form, and, when the change has become considerable enough to overcome the fortunate inertia of our perception, we say that the body has changed its form. But in reality the body is changing form at every moment; or rather, there is no form, since form is immobile and the reality i
nt? We would know above all what is going on, what the movement is doing-in other words, the result obtained or the presiding intention. Examine closely what is in your mind when you speak of an action in course of accomplishment. The idea of change is there, I am willing to grant, but it is hidden in the penumbra. In the full light is the motionless plan of the act supposed accomplished. It is by this, and by this only, that the complex act is distinguished and defined. We should be very much embarrassed if we had to imagine the movements inherent in the actions of eating, drinking, fighting, etc. It is enough for us to know, i
which are the primordial elements of language. Adjectives and substantives therefore symbolize states.
these three kinds of movement themselves-qualitative, evolutionary, extensive-differ profoundly. The trick of our perception, like that of our intelligence, like that of our language, consists in extracting from these profoundly different becomings the single representation of becoming in general, undefined becoming, a mere abstraction which by itself says nothing and of which, indeed, it is very rarely that we think. To this idea, always the same, and always obscure or unconscious, we then join, in each particular case, one or several
d attitude, it reconstitutes the mobility of the regiment marching. It is true that if we had to do with photographs alone, however much we might look at them, we should never see them animated: with immobility set beside immobility, even endlessly, we could never make movement. In order that the pictures may be animated, there must be movement somewhere. The movement does indeed exist here; it is in the apparatus. It is because the film of the cinematograph unrolls, bringing in turn the different photographs of the scene to continue each other, that each actor of the scene recovers his mobility; he strings all his successive attitudes on the invisible movement of the film. The process then consists in extracting from all the movements peculiar to all the figures an impersonal movement abstract and simple, movement in general, so to speak: we put this into the apparatus, and we reconstitute the individuality of each particular movement by c
eidoscopic picture. Our activity goes from an arrangement to a rearrangement, each time no doubt giving the kaleidoscope a new shake, but not interesting itself in the shake, and seeing only the new picture. Our knowledge of the operation of nature must be exactly symme
at action may always be enlightened, intelligence must always be present in it; but intelligence, in order thus to accompany the progress of activity and ensure its direction, must begin by adopting its rhythm. Action is discontinuous, like every pulsation of life;
I may begin again as often as I will, I may set views alongside of views for ever, I shall obtain nothing else. The application of the cinematographical method therefore leads to a perpetual recommencement, during which the mind, never able to satisfy itself and never finding where to rest, persuades itself, no doubt, that it imitates by its instability the very movement of the real. But though, by straining itself to the point of giddiness, it may end by giving itself the illusion of mobility, its operation has not advanced it a step, since it remains as far as ever from its goal. In order to advance with the moving reality, you must replace yourself within it. Install yourself within change, and you will grasp at once both ch
s. The arguments of Zeno of Elea, although formulated
y at least two successive positions, unless at least two moments are allowed it. At a given moment, therefore, it is at
n, its indivisible mobility. Suppose an elastic stretched from A to B, could you divide its extension? The course of the arrow is this very extension; it is equally simple and equally undivided. It is a single and unique bound. You fix a point C in the interval passed, and say that at a certain moment the arrow was in C. If it had been there, it would have been stopped there, and you would no longer have had a flight from A to B, but two flights, one from A to C and the other from C to B, with an interval of rest. A single movement is entirely, by the hypothesis, a movement between two stops; if there are intermediate stops, it is no longer a single movement. At bottom, the illusion arises from this, that the movement, once effected, has laid along its course a motionless trajectory on which we can count as many immobilities as we will. From this we conclude that the m
ss the same fundamental absurdity. But the possibility of applying the movement to the line traversed exists only for an observer who keeping outside the movement and seeing at every instant the possibility of a stop, tries to reconstruct the real movement with these possible immobilities. The absurdity vanishes as soon as we adopt by thought the continuity of the real movement, a continuity of which every one of us is conscious whenever he lifts an arm or advances a step. We feel then indeed that the line passed over between two stops is described with a single indivis
em; but respect the natural articulations of the two courses. As long as you respect them, no difficulty will arise, because you will follow the indications of experience. But Zeno's device is to reconstruct the movement of Achilles according to a law arbitrarily chosen. Achilles with a first step is supposed to arrive at the point where the tortoise was, with a second step at the point which it has moved to while he was making
ng, which is fashioned after our habitual manner of thinking, leads us to actual logical dead-locks-dead-locks to which we allow ourselves to be led without anxiety, because we feel confusedly that we can always get out of them if we like: all that we have to do, in fact, is to give up the cinematographical habits of our intellect. When we say "The child becomes a man," let us take care not to fathom too deeply the literal meaning of the expression, or we shall find that, when we posit the subject "child," the attribute "man" does not yet apply to it, and that, when we express the attribute "man," it applies no more to the subject "child." The reality, which is the transition from childhood to manhood, has slipped between our fingers. We have only the imaginary stops "child" and "man," and we are very near to saying that one of these stops is the other, just as the arrow of Zeno is, according to that philosopher, at all the points of the course. The truth is that if language here were molded on
ing cross cuts therein in thought. The reason is that there is more in the transition than the series of states, that is to say, the possible cuts-more in the movement than the series of positions, that is to say, the possible stops. Only, the first way of looking at things is conformable to the processes of the human mind; the second requires, on the contrary, that we reverse the bent of our int
e softened down without changing the premisses, by saying that the reality changes, but that it ought not to change. Experience confronts us with becoming: that is sensible reality. But the intelligible reality, that which ought to be, is more real still, and that reality does not change. Beneath the qualitative becoming, beneath the ev
we have given above, we might, and perhaps we ought to, translate ειδο? by "view" or rather by "moment." For ειδο? is the stable view taken of the instability of things: the quality, which is a moment of becoming; the form, which is a moment of evolution; the essence, which is the mean form above and below which the other forms are arranged as alterations of the mean; finally, the intention or mental design which presides over the action being accomplished, and which i
what idea of reality the play of this mechanism leads. It is the very idea, we believe, that we find in the ancient philosophy. The main lines of the doctrine that was developed from Plato to Plotinus, passing through Aristotle (and even, in a certain measure, through the Stoics), have nothing accidental, nothing contingent, nothing that must be regarded as a philosopher's fancy. They indicate the
om the first terms speculation must take its start. But the intellect reverses the order of the two groups; and, on this point, ancient philosophy proceeds as the intellect does. It installs itself in the immutable, it posits only Ideas. Yet becoming exists: it is a fact. How, then, having posited immutability alone, shall we make change come forth fro
out indefinitely. In right, there ought to be nothing but immutable Ideas, immutably fitted to each other. In fact, matter comes to add to them its void, and thereby lets loose the universal becoming. It is an elusive nothing, that creeps between the Ideas and creates endless agitation, eternal disquiet, like a suspicion insinuated between two loving heartinto their own definition, that is to say, into the artificial reconstruction and symbolical expression which is their intellectual equivalent. They enter into eternity, if you will; but what is eternal in them is just what is unreal. On the contrary, if we treat becoming by the cinematographical method, the Forms are no longer snapshots taken of the change, they are its constitutive elements, they represent all that is positive in Becoming. Eternity no longer hovers over time, as an abstraction; it underl
alue. The same diminution of being is expressed both by extension in space and detention in time. Both of these are but the distance between what is and what ought to be. From the standpoint of ancient philosophy, space and time can be nothing but the field that an incomplete reality, or rather a reality that has gone astray from itself, needs in order to run in quest of itself. Only it must be admitted that the field is created as the hunting progresses, and that the hunting in some way deposits the field beneath it. Move an imaginary pendulum, a mere mathematical point, from its position of equilibrium: a perpetual oscillation is started, along which points are placed next to points, and moments succeed moments. The space and time which thus arise have no more "positivity" than the movement itself. They represent the remoteness of the position artificially given to the pendulum from its normal position, what it lacks in order to regain its natural stability. Bring it back to its normal position: space, time and motion shrink to a mathematical point. Just so, human reasonings are drawn out into an endless chain, but are at once swallowed up in the truth seized by intuition, for their extension in space and time is only the distance, s
or contingency and choice. Other metaphors, expressed by other words, might have arisen; an image is called up by an image, a word by a word. All these words run now one after another, seeking in vain, by themselves, to give back the simplicity of the generative idea. Our ear only hears the words: it therefore perceives only accidents. But our mind, by successive bounds, leaps from the words to the images, from the images to the original idea, and so gets back, from the perception of words-accidents called up by accidents-to the conception of the Idea that posits its own being. So the philosopher proceeds, confronted with the universe. Experience makes to pass before his eyes phenomena which run, they also, one behind another in an accidental order dete
nd set above the physical world a Form that was thus found to be the Form of Forms, the Idea of Ideas, or, to use his own words, the Thought of Thought. Such is the God of Aristotle-necessarily immutable and apart from what is happening in the world, since he is only the synthesis of all concepts in a single concept. It is true that no one of the manifold concepts could exist apart, such as it is in the divine unity: in vain should we look for the ideas of Plato within the God of Aristotle. But if only we imagine the God of Aristotle in a sort of refraction of himself, or simply inclining toward the world, at once the Platonic Ideas are seen to pour themselves out of him, as if they were involved in the unity of his essence: so rays stream out from the sun, which nevertheless did not contain them. It is probably this possibility of an outp
. Sometimes, indeed, they speak of an attraction, sometimes of an impulsion exercised by the prime mover on the whole of the world. Both views are found in Aristotle, who shows us in the movement of the universe an aspiration of things toward the divine perfection, and consequently an ascent toward God, while he describes it elsewhere as the effect of a contact of God with the first sphere and as descending, consequently, from God to things. The Alexandrians, we think, do no more than follow this double i
, of the whole interval between 10 and zero. But here our mind passes naturally from the sphere of quantity to that of quality. It seems to us that, a certain perfection being given, the whole continuity of degradations is given also between this perfection, on the one hand, and the nought, on the other hand, that we think we conceive. Let us then posit the God of Aristotle, thought of thought-that is, thought making a circle, transformin
ll see the perfection decrease, more and more, down to our sublunary world, in which the cycle of birth, growth and decay imitates and mars the original circle for the last time. So understood, the causal relation between God and the world is seen as an attraction when regarded from below, as an impulsion or a contact when regarded from above, since the first heaven, with its circular movement, is an imitation of God and all imitation is the reception of a form. Therefore, we perceive God as efficient cause or as final cause, according to the point of view. And yet neither of these two relations is the ultimate causal relation. The true relation is that which is found between the two members of an equation, when the first member is a single term and the second a sum of an endless number of terms. It is, we may say, the
ffected by thought and language to be legitimate. What can it do, except objectify the distinction with more force, push it to its extreme consequences, reduce it into a system? It will therefore construct the real, on the one hand, with definite Forms or immutable elements, and, on the other, with a principle of mobility which, being the negation of the form, will, by the hypothesis, escape all definition and be the purely indeterminate. The more it directs its attention to the forms delineated by thought and expressed by language, the more it will see them rise above the sensible and become subtilized into pure concepts, capable of entering one within the other, and even of being at last massed together into a single concept, the synthesis of all reality, the achievement of all perfection. The more, on the contrary, it descends toward the invisible source of the universal mobility, the more it will feel this mobility sink beneath it and at the same time become void, vanish into what it will call the "non-being." Finally, it will have on the one hand the system of ideas, logically co?rdinated together or concentrated into one only, on the other a quasi-nought, the Platonic "non-being" or the Aristotelian "matter."-But, having cut your cloth, you must sew it. With supra-sensible Ideas and an infra-sensible non-being, you now have to reconstruct the sensible world. You can do so only if you postulate a kind of metaphysical necessity in virtue of which the confronting of this All with this Zero is equivalent to the affirmation of all the degrees of reality that measure the interval between them-just as an undivided number, when regarded as a difference between itself and zero, is revealed as a certain sum of units, and with its own affirmation affirms all the lower numbers. That is the natural postulate. It is that also that we perceive as the base of the Greek philosophy. In order then to explain the specifable. But an irresistible attraction brings the intellect back to its natural movement, and the metaphysic of the moderns to the general conclusions of the Greek metaphysic. We must try to make this point clear
advantage of being easily handled. But let us leave aside the means and consider only the end. What is the essential object of science? It is to enlarge our influence over things. Science may be speculative in its form, disinterested in its immediate ends; in other words we may give it as long a credit as it wants. But, however long the day of reckoning may be put off, some time or other the payment must be made. It is always then, in short, practical utility that science has in view. Even when it launches into theory, it is bound to adapt its behavior to the general form of practice. However high it may rise, it must be ready to fall back into the field of action, and at once to get on its feet. This would not be possible for it, if its rhythm
to resolve genera into laws. But we have to look at it in another aspect, which, moreover, is only a transposition, of the first. Wherein consists the difference of attitude of the two sciences toward change
rized it as a whole: it was a movement downward; it was the tendency toward a centre; it was the natural movement of a body which, separated from the earth to which it belonged, was now going to find its place again. They noted, then, the final term or culminating point (τελο? ακμη) and set it up as the essential moment: this moment, that language has retained in order to express the whole of the fact, sufficed also for science to characterize it. In the physics of Aristotle, it is by the concepts "high" and "low,"
cribing it, we are led to distinguish phases in it, we have several facts instead of a single one, several undivided periods instead of a single period; but time is always supposed to be divided into determinate periods, and the mode of division to be forced on the mind by apparent crises of the real, comparable to that of puberty, by the apparent release of a new form.-For a Kepler or a Galileo, on t
a movement by the eye and the much more complete recording of these phases by instantaneous photography. It is the same cinematographical mechanism in both cases, but it reaches a precision in the second that it cannot have in the first. Of the gallop of a horse our eye perceives chiefly a characteristic, essential or rather schematic attitude, a form that appears to radiate over a whole period and so fill up a
ng at something entirely different. The changes which are produced from one moment to another are no longer, by the hypothesis, changes of quality; they are quantitative variations, it may be of the phenomenon itself, it may be of its elementary parts. We were right then to say that modern science is distinguishable from the ancient in that it applies to magnitudes and proposes first and
circularity was sufficient to Aristotle to define the movement of the heavenly bodies. But, even with the more accurate concept of elliptical form, Kepler did not think he had acco
cover a law expressing a constant relation between magnitudes. The principle of Archimedes is a true experimental law. It takes into account three variable magnitudes: the volume of a bo
was the principle discovered by Galileo? A law which connected the space traversed by a falling body with the time occupied by the fall. Furthermore, in what did the first of the great transformations of geometry in modern times consist, if not in introducing-in a veiled form, it is true-time and movement even in the consideration of figures? For the ancients, geometry was a purely static science. Figures were given to it at once, completely finished, like the Platonic Ideas. But the essence of the Cartesian geometry (although Descartes did not give it this form) was to regard every plane curve as described by the movement of a point on a movable straight line which is displaced, parallel to itself, along the axis of the abscissae-the displacement of the
em. Each material point became a rudimentary planet, and the main question, the ideal problem whose solution would yield the key to all the others was, the positions of these elements at a particular moment being given, how to determine their relative positions at any moment. No doubt the problem cannot be put in these precise terms except in very simple cases, for a schematized reality; for we never know the respective positions of the real elements of matter, supposing there are real elements; and, even if we knew them at a given moment, the calculation of their positions at another moment would generally require a math
ts laws set forth relations between magnitudes: we must add that the magnitude to which we wish to be able to relate all others is time, and
science of matter renounces it equally. No doubt, it distinguishes as great a number of moments as we wish in the interval of time it considers. However small the intervals may be at which it stops, it authorizes us to divide them again if necessary. In contrast with ancient science, which stopped at certain so-called essential moments, it is occupied indifferently with any moment whatever. But it always considers moments,
ere no question; for there enter into the calculation only the points T1, T2, T3, ... taken on the flux, never the flux itself. We may narrow the time considered as much as we will, that is, break up at will the interval between two consecutive divisions Tn and Tn-|-1; but it is always with points, and with points only, that we are dealing. What we retain of the movement of the mobile T are positions taken on its trajectory. What we retain of all the other points of the universe are their positions on their respective trajectories. To each virtual stop of the moving body T at the points of division T1, T2, T3, ... we make correspond a virtual stop of all the other mobiles at the points where they ar
history of the world unfolded like a fan, so to speak, and the divisions T1, T2, T3, ... of the line which will be called, by definition, "the course of time." In the eyes of science nothing will have changed. But if, time thus spreading itself out in space and succession becoming juxtaposition, science has nothing to change in what it tells us, we must conclude that, in wha
physicist, since it is reduced to a certain number of units of time and the units themselves are indifferent, this duration is an absolute for my consciousness, for it coincides with a certain degree of impatience which is rigorously determined. Whence comes this determination? What is it that obliges me to wait, and to wait for a certain length of psychical duration which is forced upon me, over which I have no power? If succession, in so far as distinct from mere juxtaposition, has no real efficacy, if time is not a kind of force, why does the universe unfold its successive states with a velocity which, in regard to my consciousness, is a veritable absolute? Why with this particular velocity rather than any other? Why not with an infinite velocity? Why, in other words, is not everything given at once, as on the film of the cinematograph? The more I consider this point,
given. It is because the picture is already created, and because to obtain it requires only a work of recomposing and rearranging-a work that can be supposed going faster and faster, and even infinitely fast, up to the point of being instantaneous. But, to the artist who creates a picture by drawing it from the depths of his soul, time is no longer an accessory; it is not an interval that may be lengthened or shortened without the c
e with their essence. So of the works of nature. Their novelty arises from an internal impetus which is progress or succession, which confers on succession a peculiar virtue or which owes to succession the whole of its virtue-which, at any rate, makes succession, or continuity of interpenetration in time, irreducible to a mere instantaneous juxtaposition in space. This is why the idea of reading in a present state of the material universe the future of living forms, and of unfolding now their history yet to come, involves a veritable absurdity. But this absurdity is difficult to bring out, because our memory is accustomed to place alongside of each o
t puts on a new form and which communicates to them something of its novelty. It considers them in the abstract, such as they would be outside of the living whole, that is to say, in a time unrolled in space. It retains only the events or systems of events that can be thus isolated without being made to undergo too profound a deformation, bec
; it is the flow of time, it is the very flux of the real that we should be trying to follow. The first kind of knowledge has the advantage of enabling us to foresee the future and of making us in some measure masters of events; in return, it retains of the moving reality only eventual immobilities, that is to say, views taken of it by our mind. It symbolizes the real and transposes it into the human rather than expresses it. The other knowledge, if it is possible, is practically useless, it will not extend our empire over nature, it will even go against certain natural aspirations of the intellect; but, if it succeeds, it is reality itself that it will hold in a firm and final embrace. Not only may we thus complete the intellect and
all find that this conception of metaphys
No doubt the realization is never complete: it is this that ancient philosophy expresses by saying that we do not perceive form without matter. But if we consider the changing object at a certain essential moment, at its apogee, we may say that there it just touches its intelligible form. This intelligible form, thi
we study are the things which flow. It is true that of this flowing reality we are limited to taking instantaneous views. But, just because of this, scientific knowledge must appeal to another knowledge to complete it. While the ancient conception of scientific knowledge ended in ma
does not endure, the second bearing on duration itself. Now, it was natural to hesitate between so novel a conception of metaphysics and the traditional conception. The temptation must have been strong to repeat with the new science what had been tried on the old, to suppose our scientific knowledge of nature completed at once, to unify it entirely, and to give to this unification, as the Greeks had already done, the name of metaphysics. So, beside the new way that philosophy might have prepared, the oldven from all eternity. But, on the other hand (and that is why the philosopher has not gone to these extreme consequences), Descartes believes in the free will of man. He superposes on the determinism of physical phenomena the indeterminism of human actions, and, consequently, on time-length a time in which there is invention, creation, true sappeared not simply as continued, but also as continuous. The universe, regarded as a whole, would really evolve. The future would no longer be determinable by the present; at most we might say that, once realized, it can be found again in its antecedents, as the sounds of a new language can be expressed with the letters of an old alphabet if we agree to enlarge the value of the letters and to attribute to them, retro-actively, sounds which no combination of the old sounds could have produced beforehand. Finally, the mechany sure of its speculative impotence to renounce it in metaphysics. But ancient philosophy also influenced the choice. Artists for ever admirable, the Greeks created a type of supra-sensible truth, as of sensible beauty, whose attraction is hardir genius and the acquisitions of modern thought. And there are in each of them, especially in Spinoza, flashes of intuition that break through the system. But if we leave out of the two doctrines what breathes life into them, if we reinstrument of research, and are ignorant of the limits of its applicability, we should act as if its applicability were unlimited; there will always be time to abate it. But the temptation must have been great for the philosopher to hypostatize this hope, or rather this impetus, of the new science, and to convert a general rule of method into a fundamental law of things. So he transported himself at once to the limit; he supposed physics to have become complete and to embrace the whole of the sensible world. The universe became a system of points, the position of which was rigorously determined at each instant by relation to the preceding instant and theoretically calculable for any moment whatever. The result, in short, was universal mechanism. But it was
own, and gathered them up into a single concept, form of forms, idea of ideas, like the God of Aristotle. The new philosophy was going to take each of the laws which condition a becoming in relation to others and which are as the permanent
l into two halves, quantity and quality, the former being credited to the account of bodies and the latter to the account of souls. The ancients had raised no such barriers either between quality and quantity or between soul and body. For them, the mathematical concepts were concepts like the others, related to the others and fitting quite naturally into the hierarchy of the Ideas. Neither was the body then defined by geometrical extension, nor the soul by consciousness. If the φυχη of Aristotle, the entelechy of a living body, is less spiritual than our "soul," it is because his οωμα, already impregnated with the Idea, is less corporeal than our "body." The scission was not yet irremediable between the two terms. It has become so, and thence a metaphysic that aims at an abstract unity must resign itself either to comprehend in its synthesis only one half of the real, or to take advantage of the absolute heterogeneity of the two
f view, and it is natural for an imperfect mind like ours to class views, qualitatively different, according to the order and position of points of view, qualitatively identical, from which the views might have been taken. In reality the points of view do not exist, for there are only views, each given in an indivisible block and representing in its own way the whole of reality, which is God. But we need to express the plurality of the views, that are unlike each other, by the multiplicity of the points of view that are exterior to each other; and we also need to symbolize the more or less close relationship between the views by the relative situation of the points of view to one another, their nearness or their distance, that is to say, by a magnitude. That is what Leibniz means when he says that space is the order of coexistents, that the perception of extension is a confused perception (that is to say, a perception relative to an imperfect mind), and that nothing exists but monads, expressing thereby that the real Whole has no parts, but is
relations are ultimately summed up, and which is the basis of the unity of nature, cannot, therefore, be transcendent to sensible reality; it is immanent in it, and we must suppose that it is at once both in and out of time, gathered up in the unity of its substance and yet condemned to wind it off in an endless chain. Rather than formulate so appalling a contradiction, the philosophers were necessarily led to sacrifice the weaker of the two terms, and to regard the temporal aspect of things as a mere illusion. Leibniz says so in explicit terms, for he makes of time, as of space, a confused perception. While the multiplicity of his monads expresses only the diversity of views taken of the whole, the history of an isolated monad seems to be hardly anything else than the manifold views that it can take of its own substance: so that time would consist in all the points of view that each monad can assume towards itself, as space c
latter within the sensible-a science one and complete, with which any reality that the sensible may contain is believed to coincide. For both, reality as welld. It shows us the interdependence of the mental and the physical, the necessity of a certain cerebral substratum for the psychical state-nothing more. From the fact that two things are mutually dependent, it does not follow that they are equivalent. Because a certain screw is necessary to a certain machine, because the machine works when the screw is there and stops when the screw is taken away, we do not say that the screw is the equivalent of the machine. For correspondence to be equivalence, it would be necessary that to any part of the machine a definite part of the screw should correspond-as in a literal translation in which each chapter renders a chapter, each sentence a sentence, each word a word. Now, the relation of the brain to consciousness seems to be entirely different. Not only does the hypothesis of an equivalence between the psychical state and the cerebral state imply a downright absurdity, as we have tried to prove in a former essay,[110] but the facts, examined without prejudice, certainly seem to indicate that the relation of the psychical to the physical is just that of the machine to the screw. To speak of an equivalence between the two is simply to curtai
n science turns on laws, that is, on relations. Now, a relation is a bond established by a mind between two or more terms. A relation is nothing outside of the intellect that relates. The universe, therefore, can only be a system of laws if phenomena have passed beforehand through the filter of an intellect. Of course, this intellect might be that of a being infinitely superior to man, who would found the materiality of things at the same time that he bound them together: such was the hypothesis of Leibniz and of Spinoza. But it is not necessary to go so far, and, for the effect we have here to obtain, the human intellect is enough: such is precisely the Kantian solution. Between the dogmatism of a Spinoza or a Leibniz and the criticism of Kant there is just the same distance as between "it may be maintained that-" and "it suffices that-." Kant stops this dogmatism on the incline that was making it slip too far toward the Greek metaphysics; he reduces to the strict minimum the hypothesis which is necessary in order to suppose the physics of Galileo indefinitely extens
extra-intellectual origin to the terms between which the relations are established. He affirmed, against his immediate predecessors, that knowledge is not entirely resolvable into terms of int
nsciousness, by two efforts of opposite direction, raising itself and lowering itself by turns, become able to grasp from within, and no longer perceive only from without, the two forms of reality, body and mind? Would not this twofold effort make us, as
ave pointed out to a revivified Cartesianism.
ds of the understanding and the understanding itself had to be accepted as they are, already made. Between the matter presented to our intellect and this intellect itself there was no relationship. The agreement between the two was due to the fact that intellect imposed its form on matter. So that not only was it necessary to pos
parts an equal objectivity. But suppose, on the contrary, that science is less and less objective, more and more symbolical, as it goes from the physical to the psychical, passing through the vital: then, as it is indeed necessary to perceive a thing somehow in order to symbolize it, there would be an intuition of the psychical, and more generally of the vital, which the intellect would transpose and translate, no doubt, but which would none the less transcend the intellect. There would be, in other words, a supra-intellectual intuition. If this intuition exist, a taking possession of the spirit by itself is possible, and no longer only a knowledge that is external and phenomenal. What is more, if we have an intuition of this kind (I mean an ultra-intellectual intuition) then sensuous intuition is likely to be in continuity with it through certain intermediaries, as the infra-red is continuous with the ultra-violet. Sensuous intuition itself, therefore, is promoted. It will no longer attain only the phantom of an unattainable thing-in-itself. It is (provided we bring to it certain indispensable corrections) into the absolute itself that it will introduce us. So long as it was regarded as the only material of our science, it refle
limit in the direction of which material things develop, but which they do not actually attain. Nothing could be more contrary to the letter, and perhaps also to the spirit, of the Critique of Pure Reason. No doubt, knowledge is presented to us in it as an ever-open roll, experience as a push of facts that is for ever going on. But, according to Kant, these facts are spread out o
thus found to be sensuous, by definition. But between physical existence, which is spread out in space, and non-temporal existence, which can only be a conceptual and logical existence like that of which metaphysical dogmatism speaks, is there not
ne complete Being which it is supposed to manifest, is to return to Spinozism. It is, like Leibniz and Spinoza, to deny to duration all efficient action. The post-Kantian philosophy, severe as it may have been on the mechanistic theories, accepts from mechanism the idea of a science that is one and the same for all kinds of reality. And it is nearer to mechanism than it imagines; for though, in the consideration of matter, of life and of thought, it replaces the successive degrees o
. An experience of this kind is not a non-temporal experience. It only seeks, beyond the spatialized time in which we believe we see continual rearrangements between the parts, that concrete duration in which a radical recasting of the whole is always going on. It follows the real in all its sinuosities. It does no
to suggest the idea of a reality which endures inwardly, which is duration itself. So, when a philosopher arose who announced a doctrine of evolution, in which the progress of matter toward perceptibility would be traced together with the advance of the mind toward rationality, in which the complication of correspondences between the external and the internal would be followed step by step, in which change would become the very substance of
lo! he was doing something entirely different. His doctrine bore indeed the name of evolutionism; it claimed to remou
pieces. And a child who working thus with the pieces of a puzzle-picture, and putting together unformed fragments of the picture finally obtains a pretty colored design, no doubt imagines that he has produced design and color. Yet the act of drawing and painting has nothing to do with that of putting together the fragments of a pictu
in fragments which he throws to the winds; then he "integrates" these fragments and "dissipates their movement."
est and handiest to us, could be found at the very origin of materiality! The more physics progresses, the more it shows the impossibility of representing the properties of ether or of electricity-the probable base of all bodies-on the model of the properties of the matter which we perceive. But philosophy goes back further even than the ether, a mere schematic fig
e voluntary. We must then go in quest of the fluid reality which has been precipitated in this twofold form, and which probably shares in both without being either. At the lowest degree of the animal scale, in living beings that are but an undifferentiated protoplasmic mass, the reaction to stimulus does not yet call into play one definite mechanism, as in the reflex; it has not yet choice among several definite mechanisms, as in the voluntary act; it is, then, neither voluntary nor reflex, though it heralds both. We experience in ourselves something of this true original activity when we perform semi-voluntary and semi-aut
t as the end of an evolution. But when he comes to retrace this evolution, again he integrates the evolved with the evolved-failing to see that he is thus taking useless
sect, so far as intelligent, has already something of our intellect. Each being cuts up the material world according to the lines that its action must follow: it is these lines of possible action that, by intercrossing, mark out the net of experience of which each mesh is a fact. No doubt, a town is composed exclusively of houses, and the streets of the town are only the intervals between the houses: so, we may say that nature contains only facts, and that, the facts once posited, the relations are simply the lines running between the facts. But, in a town, it is the gradual portioning of the ground into lots that has determined at once the place of the houses, their general shape, and the direction of the streets: to this portioning we must go back if we wish to understand the particular mode of subdivision that causes each house to be where it is, each street to run as it does. Now, the cardinal error of Spencer is to take experience already allotted as given, whereas the true problem is to know how the allotment was worked. I agree that the laws of thought are only the integration of relations between facts. But, when I posit the facts with the shape they have f
gy and movement themselves? The philosopher must go further than the scientist. Making a clean sweep of everything that is only an imaginative symbol, he will see the material world melt back into a simple flux, a continuity of flowing, a becoming. And he will thus be prepared to discover real duration there where it is still more useful to find it, in the realm of life and of consciousness. For, so far as inert matter is concerned, we may neglect the flowing without committing a serious error: matter, we have said, is weighted with geometry; and matter, the reality which descends, endures only by its connection with that which ascends. But life and consciousness are this very ascension. When once we have grasped them in their essence by adopting their movement, we understand how the rest of reality is derived from them. Evolution appears and, within this evolution, the progressive determination of materiali
TNO
ews that we developed at length, from 1900 to 1904, in our lectures at the Collège de France, especially in a course on the History of the Idea of
ich we give here (pp. 275-298) has appeared be
of our knowledge in general ... the peculiar function of negative propositions
e may refer to the arguments of F. Evellin, which we regard as conclusive (see Evellin, Infini et quantité, Paris, 1880, pp. 63-97; cf. Revue philosophique, vol. xi., 1881, pp. 564-568). The truth is that mathematics, as we have tried to show in a former work, deals and can deal only with lengths. It has therefore had to see
to, Timae
se in this idea, so far as spatiality is concerned (see Chapt
πυντυ γινεσθαι, ο δε τω παντα ποιειν, ω? εξι? τι?, οιον το φω?. τρο
πο?. Phys. iv. 212 a 34 το δε παν εστι μεν ω? κινησεται εστι δ' ω? ου. ω? μεν γαρ
ο? εστιν εξω του ουρανου. Phys. viii.
side those admirable but somewhat fugitive intuitions
See pa
tes, Princip
es, Principes
1897-1898, we tried to bring out these resemblances. They are numerous and im
de métaphysique et de morale, Nov. 1904, pp. 895-
N
by the T
ng a self-contradicti
9, 282, 283
No
order, 23
Diso
and fre
, 228-9, 26
of the p
, 239, 240,
ess of du
ng, xi, 47, 15
becomin
licity
37, 39, 46, 51, 163
nce in Aristotle'
114-5, 127, 169, 170, 2
ions, 55, 63, 68,
y, function of vegeta
ortoise, in Ze
heritance of, 76-9, 83-
as inadequacy of, t
lity, three classes of
tiveness of
cepts,
xiii, 5, 143-4, 1
nuity of
f, in ani
of nervous s
lity of, 9
6, 136, 141-2, 156,
t and,
of, conscio
nt of, l
of matter
nt of consc
. See Intelle
ess varies with ratio o
ng of
ant to fulne
achine for,
12, 93, 188, 189, 206
144, 145, 146-7, 159
93, 195-6,
spac
the inte
ree, 200, 207,
sfaction the star
inuous with vital
s, 128
erse factors
110, 130, 132-3, 1
ism a
See Actio
00, 202, 207-8, 22
109, 111, 113, 114, 119-2
evolved div
ent lines
7-8, 59, 70, 101, 129,
usatio
eriality and intell
ogress
inadequate in
stantives and v
and philo
of, in the ide
ought, 281-3, 28
ation,
and negation
ndividual
d substan
iop
n philosop
f probable consciousnes
ion, 113-
of the
and decrease of mutabil
ar fro
of "generality" in p
rganisms, 99,
ta, paralyzing
f imitation of the living
the ambiguity of pr
he mobility characte
ive" expenditure of energy cha
enes
idea of,
Diso
rative, and tr
hy, Achilles and
an philos
of the
(De),
sible object,
medes
, 314, 316, 321, 323, 324, 3
f Zeno,
d God, in Ar
ncient and m
and impulsi
g in, 3
isibility of
Aristotle, 32
sian geom
y in, 32
313-4, 317,
aphical na
of God's t
ric sph
ts, 32
and "proces
ensible flux, 317-8, 321, 3
reality,
of becoming by. See Deg
17-9 note,
hilosophy
f Plotinu
and acci
or for
, 317-8
317-8, 320
210 note, 3
314-20, 322, 3
ian, and ancient
e, 196-7, 322-4
η,
314-22
ility of moti
ble reali
les of Plo
Plotinus
totle's philos
astronomy
rn geome
6-7, 228-9, 232, 281-2, 3
ce, 329-30, 336,
in, 307
sity
? νοησ
ing, 3
οιητικ
being, sensible
otle, 227-8 note
210 note, 316-8, 321-
316, 323, 326 n
Alexandrian
210 no
sm in
a through matter
g of beco
y, 314, 316-8,
α,
d time,
us, 3
in modern science,
space,
in Alexandrian
, 30
nd modern, 329-31
of Aristot
119-21, 126, 129, 131-2, 13
183, 187, 212, 214, 246, 252, 25
tion
tion
183, 187, 188,
ect to brain, 1
ciousness, 139-43, 180, 18
to instruments of a
intelligence, 137-8,
6, 143, 145, 146-7, 168-
onsciousness, 109, 111, 113, 119-21, 1
pect to function,
respect to ins
mobility, 109, 110, 113
ect to nature of c
urrents of the
, 181, 184
phora
s of Kant
Sympathy, Fee
is and t
1, 134,
nsciousness contra
sia,
ial instinc
he hymenoptera and of i
tionary s
bject, in philosophy
of the knowledge
atter, to the mathe
Or
medes
Ancient Philo
, of Zeno, 30
29 note, 4
, transformati
in evolutio
ate spe
matter relative t
tion,
l time
r scientific knowl
ts, 138,
ion of the creativen
ic movement, 1
d God, in Ar
n of organ
ndivi
etween association and
Soci
and dedu
inert or
rence to ancien
atiality bathing
240, 2
tual view of m
rpenetra
efence in ev
2, 148-9, 1
tinuit
in lower an
rted extension, Tension of personality, S
inte
ulsion in Greek ph
e and su
ic acti
ent of vol
224,
vement, etc., G
7, 143-4, 174,
ct and intelligence,
ttitude of the int
, J.M.,
lligence, 152,
an, 2
eso
273, 299-304, 307-8, 313-4,
philosophy,
es's philo
philosophy,
abstract beco
nd static views
o called, 164, 247-8
cessors of
Duration, Time,
140, 142, 1
hove
old,
, 176
ons of te
ent lines
26, 31-2, 43, 1
ionist
osophy,
ico-chem
ingh
, 188, 189,
relaxation of the unex
undles of qu
ymond (
zman
ocial insti
er, 1
strating indivisibil
, 110, 179-80, 183-4, 212 note,
n man and lower anim
t, 66
eference to animal
ce, Cellul
Séquar
e development of the n
et, 2
hli,
Reepen,
ration of variation fr
Aristotle, 32
in reference to ani
ns, 1
of the relation of fu
f the function of animal organi
g "something" on th
te not of freedom b
erence to animal
nce to the function of t
e function of organisms, 1
rence to the function
243, 2
try, compared w
ism, 345,
sians
inoza,
of matter by
, characteristic of inst
8, 147, 148-9, 165, 189-90, 195-7,
f, and genesis of the i
matter and of
, 147,
l, x, xiii, 48, 165
on to each other of the matt
tion of the law o
tion in Ari
iousness and
philoso
category which does not a
osophy of I
nd adaptati
olves mech
athematical functions
t, 238,
Aristotle's
Leibniz's ph
40, 4
istotle's ph
release and
containing effe
tal order
's allegory
33, 162, 166
cial cons
olonial t
on, 16
in the,
on to the
ence to vegetable immobilit
09-10, 180-1, 183-4, 212 note, 252, 253,
, 252, 253,
pinal sys
rvous
of inducti
ous to disord
Affe
4-5, 126, 169-70, 171, 252,
determ
275, 294, 300-304, 308, 313-4
hy, 313-4, 316-7, 3
ic philo
y from wi
os,
Diso
, moral,
in, 8
6, 55, 72, 74, 98,
telligenc
lustration of evoluti
ne, in pale
unction, 107-9,
143-5, 179, 180, 2
usness, 110
lis, 1
raph, 306
character of ancie
ledge, 306, 307, 312
age, 306
329-31, 336-7, 34
iven, broken by
and phys
lectualist philos
itional method is on
s thought in Aristo
ecial evol
protoplasmic,
s and an
olution, 101-2, 128-9, 133, 138, 142, 15
special instinc
sponding to the three
0
sius
acteristic of
rganized and the un
ts, instincts
er with space as in
ntellect as in
aliti
g and wi
finition of the feeli
, instinc
theory,
, microb
tion in liz
en the without and the within give
mind, the true meth
29, 153, 161
nuous experience
y with modern, 226, 228-9, 232,
tration
terpen
ved, xii, xiii, 51, 101, 103,
nd intelligen
of Instinct a
and intelle
, 96-7, 140-3, 177, 178-9
and metap
order of mathemati
flex, insti
n, intellect
nality,
es in Aristotle'
cessory to
with the s
imals
168, 175-8, 199-200
out with i
istinguishe
grasp life
concept-making
or the v
t by which the intellect
ancient philoso
ernality, Frames, I
128-9, 133, 138, 141-2, 150-1, 166
n of special instinct, 14
and finality in t
etermination,
lurality o
on of Inf
tion, ix, 5, 144, 14
as appendage
cal difference between pos
as auxiliary t
adequacy of act to
as instrument
val between possible a
zone of possible actions s
ss and loco
lugged up by ac
orpor
s as sketch
with ratio of possibl
istinguished from the consciou
ciousness of man, 139-43, 180,
orpor
por of plants, 109, 111, 113,
f instinct and
0, 262, 263,
110, 144-5
ith universal
ciousness as deman
enetrating ma
ncy of ins
and m
form
ion o
on or choic
nt of, 180
n and freed
rom, in lower forms of li
ter, 17
nciple of evo
ished from the absence
organi
s, 131,
principle
on of ener
9-42, 150-1, 156
ufactur
stic work of i
of Kant's su
ncy, 96,
Chance the, of
process in instinct, 1
tions, Vi
8-40, 154, 162-4, 258, 302, 306-
ming, 3
ange,
lution
tensi
ative pla
vital process, 13
1-11, 29,
g substa
hic lif
eal, 302
ition with ultra
ble univ
ality of s
ocession" in Alexand
rison of the, and t
5 note,
on, law o
ween mind and matt
imult
chanism, 25
ebral m
d genesis of
matter and of i
llows from the philoso
ed psycho
epresentation a
es, the measurement o
, 103, 105, 108, 114, 128-31, 161, 163-4, 178, 200, 2
es's philo
ellect
237, 239,
the inversion
ast, 5, 20-3, 2
al orde
, 29, 36, 37, 65, 100, 104-5, 161
of free act
venti
illustration of veg
paralyzing insti
, quest o
onary rank
ian, 205, 287 n
wledge
ugh becoming by
ews of
ter by perc
tal tendency, 51,
a, 19, 1
ing (by contrast)
t, 79
of evolutionary p
tionary s
51, 185, 236, 2
antagoni
isten
ating matter,
27, 51, 2
netrating
ymbol of lif
coming by the i
ity, Snapshots in
ter by perc
r, 12
e), 18 no
5, 66, 72,
sm, 56,
e, 36
the object of
in speculat
246 n
ed by matter, 208
cending
ing powers characteristi
n, related to moral spher
tronom
refractor
ideal limit o
imals
sitive spirit
re o
cs an
psychology and m
attack in ev
tive condition of mathemati
he realm of lif
rates,
nile (La), by Met
of energy, 2
patial into th
ux in ancient philosophy, 317-9,
in the successo
ty in Greek phil
, 59 n
, 26
are,
erati
céine,
osits, emanations, issues, or aspects of
orta,
0, 334, 345,
ing,
tion
minis
tion
om, 3
etry
d,
idea or co
rminis
ism, 3
ion
n abstract time an
existence, 11, 202, 2
tion the object of intell
n the dream
on in inte
n, 76-7, 129
5, 348. See Inert matter,
nt, 133,
gress, Evoluti
n from t
ntuition in p
e real in moder
of parts in an o
stematic metaphys
om being by, in ancient philosophy, 3
or lower complication
ain animal characteristic
ty of actio
tenti
relative to a
owled
g substa
tive i
the object of
ture, 127, 12
104, 222-3, 22
er, mathematical, Or
n an invention and i
smic principle oppos
54, 89, 135, 25
ent lines
between what is and what o
icity in the dre
e ine
teristic of the int
ic of percep
ty, 203, 20
103-4, 106, 107, 109, 112, 113, 116, 119, 130, 132, 1
Complementarity, etc., Schisms i
ible, 205, 220-
n, instin
mpathy
y of extens
on of intellect, 1
, 110, 118,
r in ce
, conscious
temology contrasted with the
z and Spi
and relativi
e law of co
of animals a
of Reink
eiste
180-1, 202
n, Relaxation, Dete
axatio
ch, 4
, 107,
rt, 1
, 242
Ch.,
, 199, 201, 206, 213, 216, 240, 272, 273, 276, 298-9, 308-9, 317
teness
ductio
es's philo
g of,
ility of,
ductio
e iner
the Ideas, 316-7, 319
f, 11, 1
, Invention, Time, Unfo
ference to animal
e in conceptio
za an
n evolut
?, 3
55, 72,
e mathematical orde
ilosophy,
an, issue, aspect or deposi
thing" on the canv
nts on the canvas hand
, 26, 27, 75,
parative, and t
ic life
centre of the theory of knowled
of know
he full by means
atic philo
s practical
, 242, 243, 245, 246
vation
on of, 24
lants, released by
f Plotinus
of Dries
opy,
133, 138, 140, 142, 150, 167, 1
nstincts, 138
omenali
ents in Aristotle
leatic philo
ning of
ies and acts, the three kin
314, 317, 320, 324,
y of Ideas, 316-
a's philo
ena,
in, 3
actions
sible a
-30, 131-2, 133, 134, 136, 138-40, 141-2, 143, 161, 166, 167, 168-72, 173, 174, 175, 179, 181, 182, 185, 186, 190,
4, 169, 170, 17
gress toward
tendencies in
rminate, is action
alleys
y of each
the divergent lines
essible, 49, 50, 52
, 19, 26, 37, 46,
36, 37, 65, 100, 105, 161, 16
of, 50, 133, 174,
t by, 133,
i, 53, 54, 87, 97-101,
on, 20, 22
centre of the theory of
133, 138, 142, 150, 167, 168,
ct, 170,
Culminating points, etc.,
53, 186, 189-90, 193,
lminating points, etc., Genes
venti
264, 2
nating po
le of, is cons
he vital impetus oppose
ansfor
le, 47, 48,
3, 68, 72 note, 85, 131,
tive, and extensive m
ity, 133
of evolutionary rank, C
, x-xii, xiv
mutability of th
contrasted with psychic
ds toward ins
eans chan
of, upon not
221, 222, 226, 233
order, 221, 222, 226
of void or n
177, 197, 204, 229,
ustrating caus
r of animal energy
anizat
e of, by plants and us
, 203, 207, 211, 223, 236, 24
uity o
f, relative to
ween what is and wh
lity of,
property of mat
movement to
owled
s philosoph
in space
hy of Ideas, 31
2, 207, 209, 211,
a's philo
cendental Ae
of,
essence of being,
ry and qualitative mo
128, 133, 137, 141-2, 150-1, 167
lity
ts, 160, 168, 174, 17
property of mat
n distinction from in
, etc., Automati
rtebrate compared, 60
, 172
on. See C
wo fundament
being by not-being,
he full by th
the motionless, 272, 2
y of insti
matter upon co
f Aristotle and Gali
of material w
e object of intellec
day,
cy of nervous system over the
of torpor in
e conception
inct, 14
lustrating heredit
tain characte
rchids by insects,
ion of the intel
tion of the relation of st
hic, figure of abs
se, 40, 4
lves conception of
n Aristot
3, 58, 74, 88-
164, 177-8, 18
and int
vital, 177, 2
seeableness of
el, 7
of animal tendency
e elements, 107-9, 1
-13, 118, 1
To
or rela
e and the, of pla
tensi
108-13, 118
id anim
and human int
f life, 15
as a whole
aterial b
250, 251,
w of Zeno,
on of pers
-4, 117, 120, 12
ilure of certain
41, 149, 150, 1
verse to m
tal force, 126, 1
as, 3
, 176
28, 29, 30, 3
oreseea
53, 155, 156, 160, 164, 195-7, 222, 237, 250, 255, 3
evolved, xi, 51, 101, 1
forms of consci
and acts the three kind
orm in Aristo
ient philosoph
148, 165, 190, 195, 196, 198, 2
Co
in creati
in knowledg
view of tra
knowled
ic,
sensibi
speci
r, 12
tion of animal
, 48, 150-2, 173, 177, 197-9, 219
inert,
to reality
xiii, xiv, 46, 48, 173,
t of l
eedom into n
their unlimited appl
, 207, 208, 217, 223, 231, 237, 239, 247, 249
e as freely
by consci
stic rather than
te not of, but
onsciousness with, 1
and life,
ss of, 223
s's philoso
ent causa
of neces
of consciousn
nment of co
164, 200, 218, 231,
r in
every orga
of, into ne
o self-negatio
, 201, 202, 207
e understanding i
ponta
lligence aroun
round intellec
ion around real
n imitation of org
thinking the, b
127, 132, 140, 141, 145, 152, 153, 157, 161, 163, 164, 168, 173-5, 186-92, 199,
the function of veget
x, 12, 44, 47, 93, 161, 162
f nervous sys
106, 107, 120,
zation of energy, 93
organisms, 107, 113
n, 107-9, 114
g the, of int
ss: sketching
n the, of i
ction, of percept
, 12, 44, 46, 93, 160, 162,
nce: concept
: construction,
: division, 154
ination of action by p
e: repetition,
ce: retrospec
nnecting same with
anning the rhythm o
tactualizing al
e: unification
s system: act
0, 94, 95, 132-
tion and
ropods, vertebrat
6-10, 112, 114, 117, 12
imentation, 106, 10
: canalization of energ
arbon in, 107, 113
hyllian function, 107-9,
ctions of life: storage and
etable: accumulation
the evolutionary movement o
ence,
ents the, of co
5, 76, 86, 88-91, 93, 94, 96, 118, 1
perception the,
ism: accumulation
two: storage and expe
ogeneity of
e on metaphy
on modern sc
Galileo's phy
bodies compared with Arist
ient fishes, in reference
y, 13
ion of, to in
, to laws,
tial,
sign
of the idea of, in p
ependent on repe
from transfere
mathematical orde
ity of structure between gene
xiv, 153, 186-1
153, 186, 187, 190, 193,
owled
, 153, 186, 188, 190
he willed or
. See
is the object of
tion or lower complication of
, Relation
ency of, and v
hematic
f, to the spatial
latent, of intel
itness of,
ctual operation
duction and deduc
cending moveme
d with ancient,
l, 194
mpregnated w
sted with reasoning
ific,
sposition of, in Neo-D
ontinuity of,
rd,
rganic funct
organic fu
activi
196, 322, 325,
in Aristotle's
thought, in Aristotle
s's philoso
se in Aristotle'
the unity of natu
philosophy, 3
al matte
form, 19
s philosoph
phy. See Anci
ants, 107-9, 114,
ng ol
eation is,
ovelt
rs of life,
ty is
niverse,
, P.,
tration of hereditar
nsciousness
a habit or bent
, 78, 93, 16
characters, i
an intelli
tion in a
ntion in
edom to self-ne
ife, and between intelligence
entarity due to a common origin
blished,
l finalis
Di
g, 60
t flint, and hum
ius-vector in Ke
on, 76-83, 87, 168-9,
on of anima
79, 83, 1
oice, consciousn
cal structures on diverg
ns, 7
, 6, 15, 21, 26, 29, 36, 37,
losoph
an organ
ignation of hum
y of space
e of inte
in Gal
rating the objec
ay, 1
animal att
l brain,
, 139-43, 180, 183, 184,
ruments of acti
igence, 138, 187,
ion, relation of,
and lang
nd manufact
, 134, 137-9, 142, 14
4-
nating po
volution,
ley
individu
Aristot
on of arthropod and instin
logists,
n and insti
stinct of, 14
stincts o
nity of nature, God
s characteristic of inte
nt philosophy, 49, 31
philosophy,
philosophy,
in Desca
lism
assume the possibility of a
rgent lines of evolution, 55
on the function of p
idea in De
d from conce
ng in Greek phil
by science,
tation, 4, 33, 88-9, 101, 176, 2
he unorganiz
lligence, 305, 30
ion of the
al order by t
intelligence,
y of exte
108-13, 11
and torpid
apparent; mob
duration a
ing ca
-7, 51-5, 97-105, 110, 118-9, 126
ness of, 126,
ded with m
ssity for crea
ugh organisms, 25, 27, 79, 8
ee Impul
, is natural: the hum
al, 137-
nction of intell
intelligence
intelligence o
, 141,
d, 141,
d, 137-9,
t knowl
ect and perception
f consciousnes
, 27, 51-5, 97-105, 110, 118-9, 12
of, 126, 141
with ma
o mobility
y for creat
itself,
in evolu
d in our
rations of organisms, 25
f, 202,
raction in Greek
ding, the three k
mind by m
o representation, c
d adequate in
ting primacy of ner
erenc
of order,
atur
f free act with conc
nd intelligen
of developed ten
ariable, time
, 86, 114, 126,
dent in
ism in Des
lligence as aggregate of m
sion of
t biology, 169
enus,
philos
uition only a
iety, 2
vital impetus,
r absolute, x, 12,
, 15-23
cs tends to deny
eration of outlines, Solida
erality
he one in the
possible in
ever absolute,
le in contrast with
y of li
k of matter, 2
lity of ac
ation,
venti
e, 225
Un
of motio
n in ani
d as factors approach p
urati
ectatio
ideal limit o
asoning, "Descending" m
nitude,
ristic function of inte
pace,
he ideal limit
ix, 161,
ion, 96, 136, 141, 1
tle, 316,
174, 186, 188, 189, 204, 213, 215, 228,
Inert matter the
186, 265,
48, 149, 15
is of
neity
living matter
physical orde
neity of
, 165, 167-8, 175, 179, 181, 186, 187,
70, 31
, 94, 98, 99, 128-9, 153, 177, 186, 189,
, 254, 256, 258, 259, 261, 264,
atter, orde
pproximate but
cs and the phssity,
153, 201, 207-12, 216, 226-7, 23
atter, inve
, 25, 26, 51, 179, 181,
ption, 12
, 201, 202, 205,
s of, 188, 202, 207, 2
, 189, 204-11, 214
r's philo
ia, 1
elligence i
eginning of i
n evolutionar
, possibl
, conjuga
eye from its stage
ividuat
cal explana
e functi
ed characters. See He
wledge, 14
the categori
atter. See
rous plan
131, 134, 135, 140-1, 146, 1
nct in hymenopt
and instinct
stinct with orga
of instinc
general in
e of an
f instin
stinct in, 14
inct in, 10
s as variations
opods in
e variati
intuitive act, contrasted with it
210
Symp
70, 84, 89, 199, 201-2, 207, 226, 249, 258
tion on inert m
distinguished
ells
143-5, 166, 167,
f, in evoluti
evolution, Evolu
lity of
in general,
, 116-8, 132-7, 141-3, 145, 150, 152, 15
259,267, 268,
ion, 177,
165, 168, 172-9, 18
138-40, 145, 166-8, 171-
rtain hymenoptera
nts, 1
insects, 10
owledge, 148,
ning
s, 192, 26tion as, of co
ural; human ar
ty as instrument
ess as, of
of intelligence is to const
transforms li
nsforms matter i
s of intelligence are artifi
instruments of inst
152-7, 162, 179, 186, 187, 192, 195, 197-8, 219, 220,
imals
eption of the
93, 126, 137-45, 149-60, 162-4, 168, 17
1, 270, 290, 298, 299, 328, 336,
126-7, 152, 153, 186, 187, 189, 193,
46, 49, 51, 86, 88-91, 93, 94, 103-4, 113
185, 190-204, 207-12, 216-8, 221, 22
276, 277, 313, 330,
158-60, 258, 265, 292,
, 136, 141, 142, 152-4, 155, 160, 161, 1
0, 213, 215, 218-20, 224, 225-30, 240
, 306, 319, 321, 329, 340, 341
9, 70, 84-5, 88-9, 101, 137-8, 150-5, 1
8, 223-40, 244, 246-7, 249-51, 254, 25
337, 338, 339, 341-8, 351, 3
1, 30, 31, 34, 35, 37, 46-9, 52, 71, 74,
, 190, 193-211, 213, 216-20, 223, 224,
, 270, 271, 273, 274, 298-314, 318-22,
-61, 363,
61-2, 168, 176-7, 188, 189, 205, 207
301, 30
, 300-1, 306-7,
157-8, 159, 160-1, 162-3, 168, 173-6, 1
7-8, 306, 321, 322, 329, 333-5, 345,
9-
74-5, 176-7, 189, 202-4, 207-12, 215,
6
-2, 36, 39, 45-6, 47, 51, 16
xii, xiii, 48, 152, 177-8, 193-4,
sophy, In
tion of Descartes betwe
137-41, 150, 154-5, 161,
138, 187
s of, x,
child
sciousn
of, 130, 1
uperi
f, 136, 1
indivi
141, 142, 168-70, 173-7, 179,
philosop
aws,
tions
2, 175, 179, 181, 186, 189, 1
of, 152, 1
159-60, 274, 30
-56, 161, 162,
-xv, 137-9, 141, 150-1,
161-2, 177, 237, 251
, 175, 176,
, 157, 15
spac
t, Understan
ntrasted with the me
lity in ancient
d, 1
les of Plo
of knowled
varies with ratio of poss
ontrasted with
led order of life the ob
on, unive
cause of v
tion of "noug
tion, r?l
l final
instinct, 168
condition of knowledge of
177, 184 note, 188, 189, 201-3, 207
ty an, of positivity, 2
rse rela
of time,
what might be done cove
between sensible and u
nd, in phil
as inversion
nucleus of intellect
inct, 17
theoretical knowl
logy as reversed
th intellectual or system, apparent vicious c
sm in Spin
ualism in Des
ousness as, and f
s of, 164,
een, and its conse
ion a
as, 102-3,
or o
ibility
a beginn
al, 142-
ne as epoch-m
as,
eablenes
nging
e
173-4, 177-8, 201, 202, 206-7, 208, 210-1, 212, 217, 218, 222, 223,
y of duration.
er, 204, 213, 215, 241,
Bo
Paul, 6
ngs,
the two kinds
n, 207-8, 33
Succ
opic vari
nomies of,
Kant's suc
ith space in Kant's phi
method of Kant's
ure reason, 205, 2
ng in Kant's s
Kant's succe
n Kant's philo
ument in Kant's
in Kant's phi
pence
r, Sensuous manifo
nism,
enesi
, 228-
n, 150, 193-4, 196,
ism of
inuity
sion
148, 194-
mal
is of
r natura
144, 166-9, 173, 1
, 179, 193-4, 196-9, 206-7, 208, 218, 23
, 342, 343, 347
ion of
internality of subject
n theoretical knowledge,
194-5, 35
xi, 48, 2
147, 148, 159-60, 163, 16
al proble
n requirements of the
93-4, 196-8,
77, 179, 197, 204-
142-6, 146,
ness of the thing-
er, 26
é 26
f, 99, 110, 118,
André,
rck,
m, 75-6,
-60, 258, 265, 293, 3
lace
gence, instinc
, 140, 145
ism of intelle
orrelati
era, 22
ius-vector in Ke
laws upon consciousness i
onal philos
ed with the laws o
sion of the nega
tical form of, 21
as, 228
instinctiv
tec, 1
, cause
sm of,
on in,
351, 3
in, 348, 3
systematization
in,
ogy in
in, 3
era, 114
Ed., 2
consciousness,
y. See
ctivity,
he realm o
, 25-6, 27, 51-5, 97-105, 110, 113, 116
4-7, 266, 27
xtensive with, 18
of the orders of
1-11, 29, 30,
61-2, 223, 230, 246,
by a curve,
yoni
, 44, 89, 16
, 153, 165,
ee, 1
, 113, 114, 117, 120, 121
alm of, 50, 51, 1
of the ine
of, by the
prolonged in
, 85, 87, 88, 127-8, 149, 195-6, 230,
ndivi
ility of,
165-8, 170, 172, 173, 175-9
, 101, 102-3, 104-5, 127, 136, 152, 160-
25-6, 257-61, 266, 270, 300-
rpenetra
177, 186, 190, 191, 196, 197, 201, 202
235, 236, 238, 239,
, 126, 127, 141
emory
, 27, 52, 179, 181, 18
to mobility,
chemistry, 31, 3
r plane
ential
d in the inert, 2
98, 99, 102, 112,
38, 140,
solar sys
of species,
ory of knowledge,
7, 28, 29, 37, 45-6, 47, 48, 52, 86,
f, 250,
wing over mat
ganism, Organization, Vital impetus,
ed o
nstinct and of i
scope of Galileo'
etus, 126, 127,
aria von,
trating failur
lor variati
onsciousness, 10
ility,
tion, ix, 44
mal
iv, 49, 103, 104-5, 136,
ry, ix, 16
6, 46-9, 89, 101, 152, 162-5, 194-201, 2
270, 313, 3
l, 161
umbe
ics, 319
ime,
igence, Understanding
ed with psychical and phys
s, x, 48,
al contras
Sigwart,
Plotinus
the attitude of
iculu
and intell
tural and ar
ement, I
or action, 2
tion approached as factors ap
n science
lution, at
183, 18
180, 181, 183, 185, 187
4-5, 185, 266
d invent
9, 143, 146, 174, 175,
uage
e (de),
ct, 137, 138, 145, 152-4, 159-6
on, 92, 93, 12
ition, 44
uction, So
inapplicable to life, x,
of individ
ultip
, J.,
n, 10
l knowl
ialis
inversion of s
rder. See Iner
See Iner
creative evolu
s, 35
human conven
me an illu
unt of action a
35, 40, 44,
of intel
n, 138,
5, 216, 218, 236,
of transfo
ral, 252, 253, 2
activity and
he e
ct as,
See Intellec
tentio
ic order, W
han, x, xiv
0, 37, 74, 88-96, 101, 102, 194-5, 218, 223
ers of the eighte
nce,
e development of the
sciousn
20, 21, 167, 16
stration of crisi
ife, uni
of larvae, 139
cs and du
gy, 177, 179,
influence
, 191-2, 26
ellect,
atter
al, 2
, 194-5, 198, 208-
192, 194, 195-6,
ikoff,
philosop
rating divergenc
al colo
dual, in phi
llect, 4
certain requirements of
, 202, 203, 205-6, 264
logical parallelism, Psych
edgwick,
characterizes animals, 109,
ness, 108, 11
4-5, 161-2, 163,
gent signs
ncy toward, 1
nts, 1
Mo
s, 60
e constructive work o
ompared with ancie
with ancient sci
lism
cient, 225-9, 231, 327-8, 3
sm of body and mind i
cal character of, 329,
with ancient, 329
leo's influen
pler's infl
tudes the obje
independent var
cule
ing animal tendency
tion i
60, 75, 77,
f Leibni
era
ism
weakness of de
, 123
L., 79
abstra
ations
characte
inematogr
uity o
cartes
sive and qualitativ
(i.e. abstr
y of, 306-7,
nct, 139-
159-60, 273, 274, 298, 317-
ation o
on along its cours
ility,
of evolution: con
s, cerebral, 25
gnon, quar
ssu
animal life,
, 103, 104, 185, 2
ital
and, 111, 11
07-10, 212, 246, 252, 256,
of the intellect, 15
unable to
126-7, 143, 144, 173-4, 176, 177, 209-
, 265, 2
s, 166
system, 110, 132
ts, 109
motion, Current, Tendency,
ic cosmic, 128-9, 135
Mutual inver
ty, abstra
202, 209
terpen
o life, x, 162,
stion of, of the
sudden, 28,
y of,
ometry, 19
t, 141, 1
knowledge,
, 161
sic, 216-7, 59-60, 61-5
otelian theor
n, 127-8,
relation
rence
219, 228-9, 239, 245, 264,
2, 143, 144-5, 150, 154, 155-6,
of,
diversity
0, 191, 195, 196-
cosmic,
eation, vital im
f individua
dom, 218
philoso
ction,
tter,
n, 275,
No
of mathematic
rse rela
173-4, 176-7, 209, 212, 218, 223-4,
ition of the two ultima
m, 55, 56, 8
arckism
of action, 109, 130-1, 1
e pla
f, 120-1,
d indeterm
, 164, 165, 199-200, 218,
omen
ton
ction of organisms,
ησι? of Ar
tence. S
g. See
the, 273-80, 281-3, 28
on, Pseudo
ικο? of Ar
ty. S
s the luminous, envelo
bial col
olid, bathed by a mis
entor
ing degrees of r
c of
l flig
ixation of, 107-9, 11
Zool.),
f this b
t, 146-52,
, 190-1, 199-200, 237, 250, 252, 270,
the condition of knowledge
ge, 147, 1
that of universal inter
t of science, 195-6, 220-1, 225-6, 227
e, 329, 3
lines in the real,
Lamarckian
owing.
of the intellect,
the idea of indi
Un
argument i
movements, 128-9, 175-6, 179, 186, 2
tion of the phys
instinc
nd acti
the two orders, 1
al inversion of
ncy of the two
, 103-4, 220-2,
6, 201, 202, 206-9, 211, 212, 216-8, 2
56, 257, 258, 264,
1, 217-9, 223-6, 230-3,
e, 225-6
ction, 222
, 222-7, 230, 23
d, 22
88-91, 93-4, 95, 132
tion and physic
141-2, 149, 162-3, 19
, and the inorganic,
f, 50-1, 103, 10
nct the proc
on, 123-4, 125, 1
itive, 99, 112, 1
on of org
nd the,
gence and instinct in the,
the, 162, 250,
the, 111, 145, 1
actual chemical nat
ion of parts
ism, comp
artificial inst
roperty of ev
, 93-4, 106-110, 113, 114, 117, 120, 12
1, 254, 255,
74, 75, 76-7, 86, 88-91, 93-4, 95, 96-7,
2,
similarity among organi
as,
15, 23, 26-7, 42, 149, 195-6,
netration of o
of the, 31
hy and t
of the
ion, 142, 145, 147-
on, 5-6,
e charac
6, 150, 165-7, 171-2, 1
tellec
re, 92, 93, 9
een the antagonistic cosm
otio
ception
of the wille
nesis,
association and indi
Soci
her,
telligence about a
g space and time in anci
ion of inner and ou
in ancient philosoph
on, 5, 11, 12, 93, 188, 189, 204-5, 206
114, 2
ogy, 24-5
oic er
-physiological, 180
in hymenoptera, 13
6, 108, 109,
itism
vity,
, in present, 4, 20-
m, 173
al structures in divergent l
social nature of
e function of t
n, recipro
terpen
11, 12, 93, 188, 189, 206,
ming, 17
character of, 206-
ess of, 2
metry,
llusc
anizati
n intellect
ion i
llection
ality, 204,
of, 299
cienc
an illusi
on,
, Ed.,
absolute re
ation of
tter,
t of intu
of, 199,
Boucher
us, 15
nd external
is and gro
nd problems, 17
on contrasted with scie
hy and a
ogy, 43-
erience
, 93-4, 168, 173-4, 194
ry of
onscious of it
ual min
tellec
and intuit
176-7, 191-4
191-2, 19
ct o
organi
sics, 1
hology,
175, 196-7,
, Finalism, Mechanistic philosoph
ntian p
strating "unwin
, consciousness
e nature of the intellectua
illustrating the mechanism
contrasted with logic
form artificial, 2
egative cosmic
object of intel
tion of, by
nce,
y and organic d
, 29-30, 34, 35,
t, "logic spoil
losophy, 315,
228 note, 324
ductio
leo, 35
ality of bod
ted psyc
ic, 319
physics,tabili
s of,
d adaptation, 6
redity
ain animal chara
on the object of intellec
life in o
-39, 142-3, 144, 145-6, 147, 168, 16
of, to animals
11, 113, 120, 128-35, 14
orpor
9, 113, 114, 117,
structure in,
duatio
t in, 1
109, 111-13, 118-
lution with animal
s of all
ion of
ty of germinativ
substa
note, 316, 318, 319, 32
49, 315-6, 321,
, 314-5, 323, 324
confused, o
terpen
to perception; the sense i
reation of mat
ου?, of Ari
f ants, bees,
t societ
zois
ity, 208, 212
inversion or interruption
n consciousness, 11, 12, 96, 14
1, 189,
nce, 2
n philosoph
ivity. See Po
era
e, 142-7
life as an imm
nding acts, 179
sible a
1-5, 97-105, 110, 113, 116-8, 119, 126-7, 131-6, 140-3,
intellect and science, 137-41, 150, 193-4, 196, 197,
hed harmony
f, by past, 5, 20-3
n. See F
ervous syste
nstinct,
mbiguous forms of, 99,
n Alexandrian
daptation a
134, 138, 141-2, 173-
strating the two kind
s, coloniz
circulation
escence
on of,
the nervous sys
organisms,
ital prin
associatio
ng o
guous f
iduation,
lanation of mo
vous sy
uction
d problems, 177
a, division of
Aristo
inus, 2
twofold nature of,
inuity of,
ntrasted with logical,
of li
erted physic
tion of the phys
and deduc
of intellect, 18
osmology as r
l parallelism, 180,
ting crises in ev
utionary and exte
302-3,
s, the classes of rep
bundles
dence
ements,
ral geom
ion of, in i
is chang
c philoso
in ancient ph
in modern p
hythm
ry subst
, René,
eliocentric, in
onary, 50, 13
e of, in perc
xiv, 48, 237, 250, 251, 27
distinguished f
continuous exper
y of the,
he, in modern
intelligence, 90, 2
tlines in the, 11-
n of the, by
, ancie
ke assume possibility of a
, 198, 228-9, 230
47, 191-2
s of,
ic metaph
f, 179-80, 21
on, 11-2,
250, 251, 294,
of the intell
of the un
eedom
ancient phi
rowt
by the intelle
52, 89-90, 153, 191
in ancient p
of, 307-8,
anism, 3
t, 90, 155
eing, 276
perso
h the forms of percep
196, 198, 199, 203
philosophy, 314, 31
88-9, 93-4, 195-6, 197,
e conceptu
ble in
le in Sp
01, 206-7, 225-6, 249, 258, 273, 3
life, 7,
nscend its
and acti
erience
er, 204-
r and li
nce of, on special ci
ream, 20
eption,
, of the present in the
nd, the characteristic pow
comparison of
ction
activ
d, 173-
dea through matter
forms of percepti
and individ
of time,
e, 42
relations and laws up
, 229,
156-7, 160, 161,
istemological,
y of immo
152, 153, 187, 195-6, 197-8,
dge, 152,
ion, 226-7
the dream stat
, 207-8, 209, 210,
, 200, 207-8,
virtual ge
nextended into
ishes in c
as, of f
ecommences in the sta
s in complet
Te
se, 73, 74, 1
d generalizat
ation, 44-
ect, 156-7
, 7-8, 28-9, 3
the mathematical ord
and action, 1
lities, forms,
ciousnes
303-4, 305, 306-7,
273-80, 281-4
tion distinguished from extern
and individ
ce. See S
, of energy, 115, 116
otion in Z
n in evoluti
e function of in
logy: intuition
and animal
ler,
ion, 11-2, 127-
adopts the, o
tion, 299
ualit
universe the functi
coincide with th
anslatable into scie
arthrop
tive evolution
nes,
e, 2
), Ed.,
maculata, v
sky,
ect connecting same with
d Heymons
(De),
of distance and
dilemma of any systematic me
mitive impulsion o
ent lines
sticis
ction, 93, 19
modern, 329-3
cient and mod
try and ancient
ter of modern, 329, 330,
of a certain a
ductio
ontinuit
173-4, 176-7, 193-4, 1
luence on mod
169, 170, 17
gence, 176,
fluence on
r, 194-5,
See Mode
251, 270-1, 273, 296-8, 306-
rcepti
175-6, 196-7,
cs and reality. See
, 8-13,
30, 321-2, 323, 344-5, 347-8,
c concept
philosophical
ulae
ry, 16
, 196-7, 198, 19
s and ag
alyzing ins
itely extended by intel
's physics
t, 6
and indiv
les,
instinct
ming in the philos
perception, 2
ck, 26
g, coincidence of
56-7, 59-60, 61-2, 63,
cidence of
f, means ch
dge of
e, 15-23,
n and sp
eption. Se
16-7, 318, 321,
ultra-intell
ee of, 342-3
, 317, 319,
ity, for
illustration of mo
system. See
old, 205, 221,
n illustration of in
ski, 2
n of identical evolutio
ls, 14, 26
in plants and ani
S., 133 no
llustration of animal te
tion of, 15
ent of scie
rt, 2
re of certain species
of same species the type of g
ical causa
me is merely to count simul
evolution, 71
scious knowled
magnitude, p
ts, function of c
129-31,
ntellectual representation of
y, Cinematographic
f transition, 301-2,
nct, 101, 14
8, 140,
character of n
01, 131-2, 1
the individu
by plants, released
1-4, 246 no
life in o
ts analogous
a solid nuc
and the object of the intel
n brain and consc
f matter, 203,
perated by the u
Aristo
d consciousness
nd bod
cell
ion o
nd acti
philosoph
-1, 163, 174-5, 1
trica
ity of,
ductio
losophy, 205,
z's philo
202-13, 244, 25
Kant's philo
plicity determi
Exte
here of, bathing
of the extra
ss, 203, 207,
al space, 203
atical ord
and environment, 1
ections, 1
on a theme,
articul
of, 247,
nality, 128-9,
sil
al of evolut
yled homo
t, 140, 167
life
ithin, 223-6
-locks in, xii, 1
6, 198, 220, 225-6, 227, 251, 270
, xiv, 78-9, 153, 18
correspondence between
gony
ns and laws upon c
in, 3
in, 3
ic, in Aristotle'
yzing instin
aralyzing hym
l cor
equate and the
se,
ism, 3
nity
nsio
351
tioni
, 348, 35
e,
251, 2
210-1, 212-3, 217, 218, 219, 222-3, 237, 238, 245, 247-8,
ty of lif
Fr
echan
etable
willed o
(bio
unction of veget
g, 1, 13, 163, 24
f the intellect, 1
f becom
ny, 12
onze, parallel as e
d individu
ics
r energy by pla
nd indivisibili
ration as
nction. See Func
evolution, 55, 60, 61-2, 63, 69,
nd attrib
, albumin
ty of li
40, 142, 149, 162-3,
a's philo
substa
bs, correspond to the three c
resentation of the Nought, 28
physics,
iority, 1
10, 339, 340, 341, 3
s of Kant
ions, 28, 62
15, 24
existence upon
pon disord
Measurement of qualit
volutionary, 1
rman
nscious
of the
ural se
, as instinctive
oncept is a,
1, 88-9, 93, 195-6, 210
ledge of life
m, 176,
ntuitive knowled
nct is, 164, 16
on, Feeling,
ysics, dilemma ofional, 191-2, 193-4, 2
te of,
f physics, Liebni
-13, 203, 214, 215,
logy with deduction an
hysico-chemist
itch, 1
gy. See
tendencies of life, 13,
es in development of
cies of life, 51, 10
sociat
89, 99, 101, 107-8, 109-10, 112, 1
ividua
y to act on in
als, 109, 110, 113, 127
sts in prese
produ
s to chan
ymbols of tend
stems, in
ssion o
property
d extensio
0-2, 207-8, 223
inversion o
199-200, 201, 20
substa
ent upon philoso
fallacie
and instin
lect, 155, 177, 179
riginal function of
, 178, 180, 184-5, 197, 2
xiii, 178
ynamics
of energy, Degr
nd antit
d from motion, 187, 2
, 147, 148, 150, 152, 158-9, 1
mind
n operated by un
elf, 205, 20
us, 3
olute, 240, 241,
, 21, 22
ions of r
, 45-6, 47,
, 17, 18, 1
ent variabl
l of, 9
ention
philosophy,
ogic,
neity, 9, 3
science 32
ce in K
ncient philoso
Dura
ntellect, 1
Impl
109, 111, 113, 114 not
illes and the
presses all perce
intelligence t
tion along its c
ental Aes
n, 32, 72, 73
ormism
pshot view of, 301-2,
d characters, 75-84, 87, 16
7, 79, 85, 87, 88, 93-4, 110, 126-7, 128
n of motor me
egenerati
sychical acti
d in intuit
ious ef
2-3, 144, 14
ge, 145
ness, two k
le, reali
uteness of, 153-4, 1
ion, ix
-xv, 49, 189, 207-
metry,
s of categori
tuitio
101, 147-8, 149, 152, 162-5, 173-4, 17
, 266, 270, 271
, 168, 179, 194-5, 19
48, 237, 250, 251, 273,
he so
ope of the,
Concept, Categories, Frames
determinate evolutio
ng caus
bleness of
ion, 6,
n, 47, 48,
venti
fe, 1
lled order
Fore
unction of the intel
f phases of
f exten
wledge
106-7, 25
tal li
as determinatio
-90, 191, 195-6, 197,
organis
228-9, 230, 321, 322,
interactio
ss coextensive wi
continui
rtes'
the idea of di
of, 10,
of, 241,
of, 342
f, in Aris
ity of,
anism,
zation o
f, 337,
sidered by sci
on of physic
the, of evol
ant, 204,
process of materiality, 24
odies, 7-8, 1
nert
s, 137-9,
n, and the organized
of the organized
nd scien
See iner
ing ca
in Greek philo
ng of inv
5, 158-9, 160, 168, 187, 195
Vanessa prorsa, t
e as an indep
dental, 55, 63-
in lizar
ation,
3-4, 72 note, 131-2, 13
ible,
as cause
ants,
kingdom.
tion expre
ntives and ad
lustration of the two
ix, 126, 130
er analyzed into
parent, of intuiti
alism, 194, 1
ecoming, 4, 90-1, 273, 2
matter, 203, 24
ality
, P.,
l acti
ssible
etry
usness compre
in Alexandrian
See Eye of
andra ma
134-6, 139, 140,
, 87, 88, 96-105, 118-9, 120,
5, 118-9, 126-7, 128, 131-2, 141-2, 14
254-5
e in, 34, 3
ality and,
and in the mathematical orde
l order, 222-3, 225, 226,
of physical ord
, 42, 43,
l and the mathematical orders
ess,
ism,
274, 275, 277-8, 281, 283-4, 2
sin
cerebral me
activity
), 24, 63
stinct in
and inte
n, 26,
nd cap
ral mecha
penetratin
, into reali
xation,
ism in dis
f, 199, 2
ngency of willed order and
ility in th
nce of seeing and
n, E.
f, 7
d states
nding to three classes of
ntelligi
conciousnes
n of ambiguity of pri
hex, paralyzing
motion
ies surrounding act
ogy,
in illustration of m