Login to MoboReader
icon 0
icon TOP UP
rightIcon
icon Reading History
rightIcon
icon Log out
rightIcon
icon Get the APP
rightIcon
The philosophy of B*rtr*nd R*ss*ll

The philosophy of B*rtr*nd R*ss*ll

Various

4.0
Comment(s)
42
View
43
Chapters

The philosophy of B*rtr*nd R*ss*ll by Various

Chapter 1 THE INDEFINABLES OF LOGIC

The view that the fundamental principles of logic consist solely of the law of identity was held by Leibniz,[2] Drobisch, Uberweg,[3] and Tweedledee. Tweedledee, it may be remembered,[4] remarked that certain identities "are" logic. Now, there is some doubt as to whether he, like Jevons,[5] understood "are" to mean what mathematicians mean by "=," or, like Schr?der[6] and most logicians, to have the same meaning as the relation of subsumption.

The first alternative alone would justify our contention; and we may, I think, conclude from an opposition to authority that may have been indicated by Tweedledee's frequent use of the word "contrariwise" that he did not follow the majority of logicians, but held, like Jevons,[7] the mistaken[8] view that the quantification of the predicate is relevant to symbolic logic.

It may be mentioned, by the way, that it is probable that Humpty-Dumpty's "is" is the "is" of identity. In fact, it is not unlikely that Humpty-Dumpty was a Hegelian; for, although his ability for clear explanation may seem to militate against this, yet his inability to understand mathematics,[9] together with his synthesis of a cravat and a belt, which usually serve different purposes,[10] and his proclivity towards riddles seem to make out a good case for those who hold that he was in fact a Hegelian. Indeed, riddles are very closely allied to puns, and it was upon a pun, consisting of the confusion of the "is" of predication with the "is" of identity-so that, for example, "Socrates" was identified with "mortal" and more generally the particular with the universal-that Hegel's system of philosophy was founded.[11] But the question of Humpty-Dumpty's philosophical opinions must be left for final verification to the historians of philosophy: here I am only concerned with an a priori logical construction of what his views might have been if they formed a consistent whole.[12]

If the principle of identity were indeed the sole principle of logic, the principles of logic could hardly be said to be, as in fact they are, a body of propositions whose consistency it is impossible to prove.[13] This characteristic is important and one of the marks of the greatest possible security. For example, while a great achievement of late years has been to prove the consistency of the principles of arithmetic, a science which is unreservedly accepted except by some empiricists,[14] it can be proved formally that one foundation of arithmetic is shattered.[15] It is true that, quite lately, it has been shown that this conclusion may be avoided, and, by a re-moulding of logic, we can draw instead the paradoxical conclusion that the opinions held by common-sense for so many years are, in part, justified. But it is quite certain that, with the principles of logic, no such proof of consistency, and no such paradoxical result of further investigations is to be feared.

Still, this re-moulding has had the result of bringing logic into a fuller agreement with common-sense than might be expected. There were only two alternatives: if we chose principles in accordance with common-sense, we arrived at conclusions which shocked common-sense; by starting with paradoxical principles, we arrived at ordinary conclusions. Like the White Knight, we have dyed our whiskers an unusual colour and then hidden them.[16]

The quaint name of "Laws of Thought," which is often applied to the principles of Logic, has given rise to confusion in two ways: in the first place, the "Laws," unlike other laws, cannot be broken, even in thought; and, in the second place, people think that the "Laws" have something to do with holding for the operations of their minds, just as laws of nature hold for events in the world around us.[17] But that the laws are not psychological laws follows from the facts that a thing may be true even if nobody believes it, and something else may be false if everybody believes it. Such, it may be remarked, is usually the case.

Perhaps the most frequent instance of the assumption that the laws of logic are mental is the treatment of an identity as if its validity were an affair of our permission. Some people suggest to others that they should "let bygones be bygones." Another important piece of evidence that the truth of propositions has nothing to do with mind is given by the phrase "it is morally certain that such-and-such a proposition is true." Now, in the first place, morality, curiously enough, seems to be closely associated with mental acts: we have professorships and lectureships of, and examinations in, "mental and moral philosophy." In the second place, it is plain that a "morally certain" proposition is a highly doubtful one. Thus it is as vain to expect any information about our minds from a study of the "Laws of Thought" as it would be to expect a description of a certain social event from Miss E. E. C. Jones's book An Introduction to General Logic.

Fortunately, the principles or laws of Logic are not a matter of philosophical discussion. Idealists like Tweedledum and Tweedledee, and even practical idealists like the White Knight, explicitly accept laws like the law of identity and the excluded middle.[18] In fact, throughout all logic and mathematics, the existence of the human or any other mind is totally irrelevant; mental processes are studied by means of logic, but the subject-matter of logic does not presuppose mental processes, and would be equally true if there were no mental processes. It is true that, in that case, we should not know logic; but our knowledge must not be confounded with the truths which we know.[19] An apple is not confused with the eating of it except by savages, idealists, and people who are too hungry to think.

* * *

[2] Russell, Ph. L., pp. 17, 19, 207-8.

[3] Schr?der, A. d. L., i. p. 4.

[4] See Appendix A. This Appendix also illustrates the importance attached to the Principle of Identity by the Professor and Bruno.

[5] S. o. S., pp. 9-15.

[6] A. d. L., i. p. 132.

[7] Cf., besides the reference in the last note but one, E. L. L., pp. 183, 191. "Contrariwise," it may be remarked, is not a term used in traditional logic.

[8] S. L., 1881, pp. 173-5, 324-5; 1894, pp. 194-6.

[9] Cf. Appendix C, and William Robertson Smith, "Hegel and the Metaphysics of the Fluxional Calculus," Trans. Roy. Soc., Edinb., vol. xxv., 1869, pp. 491-511.

[10] See Appendix B.

[11] [This is a remarkable anticipation of the note on pp. 39-40 of Mr. Russell's book, published about three years after the death of Mr. R*ss*ll, and entitled Our Knowledge of the External World as a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy, Chicago and London, 1914.-Ed.]

[12] Cf. Ph. L., pp. v.-vi. 3.

[13] Cf. Pieri, R. M. M., March 1906, p. 199.

[14] As a type of these, Humpty-Dumpty, with his inability to admit anything not empirically given and his lack of comprehension of pure mathematics, may be taken (see Appendix C). In his (correct) thesis that definitions are nominal, too, Humpty-Dumpty reminds one of J. S. Mill (see Appendix D).

[15] See Frege, Gg., ii. p. 253.

[16] See Appendix E.

[17] See Frege, Gg., i. p. 15.

[18] See the above references and also Appendix F.

[19] Cf. B. Russell, H. J., July 1904, p. 812.

* * *

Continue Reading

Other books by Various

More
Yule Logs

Yule Logs

Young Adult

5.0

It was a grand success. Every one said so; and moreover, every one who witnessed the experiment predicted that the Mermaid would revolutionize naval warfare as completely as did the world-famous Monitor. Professor Rivers, who had devoted the best years of his life to perfecting his wonderful invention, struggling bravely on through innumerable disappointments and failures, undaunted by the sneers of those who scoffed, or the significant pity of his friends, was so overcome by his signal triumph that he fled from the congratulations of those who sought to do him honour, leaving to his young assistants the responsibility of restoring the marvellous craft to her berth in the great ship-house that had witnessed her construction. These assistants were two lads, eighteen and nineteen years of age, who were not only the Professor's most promising pupils, but his firm friends and ardent admirers. The younger, Carlos West Moranza, was the only son of a Cuban sugar-planter, and an American mother who had died while he was still too young to remember her. From earliest childhood he had exhibited so great a taste for machinery that, when he was sixteen, his father had sent him to the United States to be educated as a mechanical engineer in one of the best technical schools of that country. There his dearest chum was his class-mate, Carl Baldwin, son of the famous American shipbuilder, John Baldwin, and heir to the latter's vast fortune. The elder Baldwin had founded the school in which his own son was now being educated, and placed at its head his life-long friend, Professor Alpheus Rivers, who, upon his patron's death, had also become Carl's sole guardian. In appearance and disposition young Baldwin was the exact opposite of Carlos Moranza, and it was this as well as the similarity of their names that had first attracted the lads to each other. While the young Cuban was a handsome fellow, slight of figure, with a clear olive complexion, impulsive and rash almost to recklessness, the other was a typical Anglo-Saxon American, big, fair, and blue-eyed, rugged in feature, and slow to act, but clinging with bulldog tenacity to any idea or plan that met with his favour. He invariably addressed his chum as "West," while the latter generally called him "Carol."

You'll also like

Chapters
Read Now
Download Book
The philosophy of B*rtr*nd R*ss*ll
1

Chapter 1 THE INDEFINABLES OF LOGIC

06/12/2017

2

Chapter 2 OBJECTIVE VALIDITY OF THE "LAWS OF THOUGHT"

06/12/2017

3

Chapter 3 IDENTITY

06/12/2017

4

Chapter 4 IDENTITY OF CLASSES

06/12/2017

5

Chapter 5 ETHICAL APPLICATIONS OF THE LAW OF IDENTITY

06/12/2017

6

Chapter 6 THE LAW OF CONTRADICTION IN MODERN LOGIC

06/12/2017

7

Chapter 7 SYMBOLISM AND MEANING

06/12/2017

8

Chapter 8 NOMINALISM

06/12/2017

9

Chapter 9 AMBIGUITY AND SYMBOLIC LOGIC

06/12/2017

10

Chapter 10 LOGICAL ADDITION AND THE UTILITY OF SYMBOLISM

06/12/2017

11

Chapter 11 CRITICISM

06/12/2017

12

Chapter 12 HISTORICAL CRITICISM

06/12/2017

13

Chapter 13 IS THE MIND IN THE HEAD

06/12/2017

14

Chapter 14 THE PRAGMATIST THEORY OF TRUTH

06/12/2017

15

Chapter 15 ASSERTION

06/12/2017

16

Chapter 16 THE COMMUTATIVE LAW

06/12/2017

17

Chapter 17 UNIVERSAL AND PARTICULAR PROPOSITIONS

06/12/2017

18

Chapter 18 DENIAL OF GENERALITY AND GENERALITY OF DENIAL

06/12/2017

19

Chapter 19 IMPLICATION

06/12/2017

20

Chapter 20 DIGNITY

06/12/2017

21

Chapter 21 THE SYNTHETIC NATURE OF DEDUCTION

06/12/2017

22

Chapter 22 THE MORTALITY OF SOCRATES

06/12/2017

23

Chapter 23 DENOTING

06/12/2017

24

Chapter 24 THE

06/12/2017

25

Chapter 25 NON-ENTITY

06/12/2017

26

Chapter 26 IS

06/12/2017

27

Chapter 27 AND AND OR

06/12/2017

28

Chapter 28 THE CONVERSION OF RELATIONS

06/12/2017

29

Chapter 29 PREVIOUS PHILOSOPHICAL THEORIES OF MATHEMATICS

06/12/2017

30

Chapter 30 FINITE AND INFINITE

06/12/2017

31

Chapter 31 THE MATHEMATICAL ATTAINMENTS OF TRISTRAM SHANDY

06/12/2017

32

Chapter 32 THE HARDSHIPS OF A MAN WITH AN UNLIMITED INCOME

06/12/2017

33

Chapter 33 THE RELATIONS OF MAGNITUDE OF CARDINAL NUMBERS

06/12/2017

34

Chapter 34 THE UNKNOWABLE

06/12/2017

35

Chapter 35 MR. SPENCER, THE ATHANASIAN CREED AND THE ARTICLES

06/12/2017

36

Chapter 36 THE HUMOUR OF MATHEMATICIANS

06/12/2017

37

Chapter 37 THE PARADOXES OF LOGIC

06/12/2017

38

Chapter 38 MODERN LOGIC AND SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ARGUMENTS

06/12/2017

39

Chapter 39 THE HIERARCHY OF JOKES

06/12/2017

40

Chapter 40 THE EVIDENCE OF GEOMETRICAL PROPOSITIONS

06/12/2017